Looking Forward. By Michael Albert and Robin Hahnel

 Go to Table of Contents

 

  3. Egalitarian Consumption

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

To enjoy the things we ought, and to hate the things we ought has the greatest bearing on excellence of character.

-Aristotle

The Basic Works of Aristotle

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

Sell a country! Why not sell the air, the clouds, and the great sea as well as the earth?

-Tecumseh

Speech to Governor Harrison

 

 

 

What a sad and tragic mistake! To give full scope to socialism entails rebuilding from top to bottom a society dominated by the narrow individualism of the shopkeeper. It is not as has sometimes been said by those indulging in metaphysical woolliness just a question of giving the worker "the total product of his labor"; it is a question of completely reshaping the relationships ... in the factory, in the village, in the store, in production, and in distribution of supplies. All relations between individuals and great centers of population have to be made all over again, from the very day, from the very moment one alters the existing commercial organization.

 

 - Peter Kropotkin

 

If production is at the foundation of every economy, consumption is the living room. How consumption is organized therefore affects the quality of life just as work organization does. Under capitalism when we buy, there is every incentive to think only of ourselves while ignoring the environment, our neighbors, and especially the workers who produce what we enjoy. In fact, in capitalism it is nonsensical to consider others.

 

Eating a salad, we do not assess the plight of migrant pickers. Driving a car, we do not calculate the increased probability of cancer for children playing on the sidewalks we pass. Even as we whimsically over consume what might help others survive, we ignore the human implications of our own gluttony. We know relatively little about others. We feel relatively little for others. We do relatively little to help others. Whatever our inclinations, markets provide means for us to consider only our own welfare. Regardless of our wishes, our scramble for goods impedes solidarity.

 

Yet even within the raging individualism of our capitalist economy we can imagine a particularly close-knit family that makes collective decisions. Such a family, in contrast to the usual patriarchal situation, might together allocate funds for family purchases and decide together how much each member can spend out of what's left over. And while individual purchases by the family's members may be primarily private, this may not be entirely so.

 

For example, given this family's special solidarity, perhaps all its members understand that every consumption decision has implications extending beyond the individual doing the consuming. Consider a son buying a set of drums or father purchasing a box of cigars. Since the byproducts of those purchases, noise and smoke, will affect everyone, the purchases are not really private. More interesting, a family member's consumption may affect his or her personality and then, by way of that, everyone in his or her social orbit. Consider the result if father spends his allowance on liquor, or if a daughter spends hers playing computer Armageddon. Since the whole family will suffer, the family may justifiably intervene to maintain a subtle balance between privacy, freedom, and the need to promote an acceptable environment for everyone.

 

But these unusual family members we've dreamed up are able to weigh one another's circumstances only because they communicate considerable information to one another. Certainly few would suggest that such tight bonds could (or should) characterize relations between all citizens. After all, families actually live together. Yet if participatory economics could emulate our unusual small family's interpersonal concern for one another's well-being while simultaneously protecting each person's right to self-management and privacy, it would certainly help overcome the debilitating competition familiar to normal capitalist consumption patterns.

 

Consumption Norms

 

Some personal consumption decisions affect primarily one individual consumer and the workers who produce what he or she consumes. Other personal consumption decisions affect a broader spectrum of economic actors. The concept of an "externality," wherein an economic act affects people beyond those immediately involved is applicable in these instances and, in fact, all goods have varying degrees of external impact.

 

It follows that if every consumer is to have a say roughly proportional to the effects they feel, and if economic decisions are to promote variety and solidarity, we need a means for actors to interact with one another before decisions are reached. Moreover, for work to be socially beneficial as well as equitable, workers and consumers will have to interact as a critical part of planning their related economic activities. Though the means for consumers to interact with workers and with consumers in other councils depends on the allocation system still to be discussed, we can here address at least a means for consumers within particular councils to consider consumption requests.